Read The Fabric of the Cosmos: Space, Time, and the Texture of Reality Online

Authors: Brian Greene

Tags: #Science, #Cosmology, #Popular works, #Astronomy, #Physics, #Universe

The Fabric of the Cosmos: Space, Time, and the Texture of Reality (55 page)

BOOK: The Fabric of the Cosmos: Space, Time, and the Texture of Reality
2.02Mb size Format: txt, pdf, ePub
ads
Dark Matter, Dark Energy, and the Future of the Universe

In Chapter 10 we went through the strong theoretical and observational evidence indicating that a mere 5 percent of the universe's heft comes from the constituents found in familiar matter—protons and neutrons (electrons account for less than .05 percent of ordinary matter's mass)— while 25 percent comes from dark matter and 70 percent from dark energy. But there is still significant uncertainty regarding the detailed identity of all this dark stuff. A natural guess is that the dark matter is also composed of protons and neutrons, ones that somehow avoided clumping together to form light-emitting stars. But another theoretical consideration makes this possibility very unlikely.

Through detailed observations, astronomers have a clear knowledge of the average relative abundances of light elements—hydrogen, helium, deuterium, and lithium—that are scattered throughout the cosmos. To a high degree of accuracy, the abundances agree with theoretical calculations of the processes believed to have synthesized these nuclei during the first few minutes of the universe. This agreement is one of the great successes of modern theoretical cosmology. However, these calculations assume that the bulk of the dark matter is
not
composed of protons and neutrons; if, on cosmological scales, protons and neutrons were a dominant constituent, the cosmic recipe is thrown off and the calculations yield results that are ruled out by observations.

So, if not protons and neutrons, what constitutes the dark matter? As of today, no one knows, but there is no shortage of proposals. The candidates' names run the gamut from axions to zinos, and whoever finds the answer will surely pay a visit to Stockholm. That no one has yet detected a dark matter particle places significant constraints on any proposal. The reason is that dark matter is not only situated out in space; it is distributed throughout the universe and so is also wafting by us here on earth. According to many of the proposals, right now billions of dark matter particles are shooting through your body every second, so viable candidates are only those particles that can pass through bulky matter without leaving a significant trace.

Neutrinos are one possibility. Calculations estimate their relic abundance since they were produced in the big bang, at about 55 million per cubic meter of space, so if any one of the three neutrino species weighed about a hundredth of a millionth (10
-8
) as much as a proton, they would supply the dark matter. Although recent experiments have given strong evidence that neutrinos do have mass, according to current data they are too light to supply the dark matter; they fall short of the mark by a factor of more than a hundred.

Another promising proposal involves supersymmetric particles, especially the
photino,
the
zino,
and the
higgsino
(the partners of the photon, the Z, and the Higgs). These are the most standoffish of the supersymmetric particles—they could nonchalantly pass through the entire earth without the slightest effect on their motion—and hence could easily have escaped detection.
9
From calculations of how many of these particles would have been produced in the big bang and survived until today, physicists estimate that they would need to have mass on the order of 100 to 1,000 times that of the proton to supply the dark matter. This is an intriguing number, because various studies of supersymmetric-particle models as well as of superstring theory have arrived at the same mass range for these particles, without any concern for dark matter or cosmology. This would be a puzzling and completely unexplained confluence, unless, of course, the dark matter is indeed composed of supersymmetric particles. Thus, the search for supersymmetric particles at the world's current and pending accelerators may also be viewed as searches for the heavily favored dark matter candidates.

More direct searches for the dark matter particles streaming through the earth have also been under way for some time, although these are extremely challenging experiments. Of the million or so dark matter particles that should be passing through an area the size of a quarter each second, at most one per day would leave any evidence in the specially designed equipment that various experimenters have built to detect them. To date, no confirmed detection of a dark matter particle has been achieved.
10
With the prize still very much up in the air, researchers are pressing ahead with much intensity. It is quite possible that within the next few years, the identity of the dark matter will be settled.

Definitive confirmation that dark matter exists, and direct determination of its composition, would be a major advance. For the first time in history, we would learn something that is at once thoroughly basic and surprisingly elusive: the makeup of the vast majority of the universe's material content.

All the same, as we saw in Chapter 10, recent data suggest strongly that even with the identification of the dark matter, there would still be a significant plot twist in need of experimental vetting: the supernova observations that give evidence of an outward-pushing cosmological constant accounting for 70 percent of the total energy in the universe. As the most exciting and unexpected discovery of the last decade, the evidence for a cosmological constant—an energy that suffuses space—needs vigorous, airtight confirmation. A number of approaches are planned or already under way.

The microwave background experiments play an important role here as well. The size of the splotches in Figure 14.4—where, again, each splotch is a region of uniform temperature—reflects the overall shape of the spatial fabric. If space were shaped like a sphere, as in Figure 8.6a, the outward bloating would cause the splotches to be a bit bigger than they are in Figure 14.4b; if space were shaped like a saddle, as in Figure 8.6c, the inward shrinking would cause the splotches to be a bit smaller; and if space were flat, as in Figure 8.6b, the splotch size would be in between. The precision measurements initiated by COBE and since bettered by WMAP strongly support the proposition that space is
flat.
Not only does this match the theoretical expectations coming from inflationary models, but it also jibes perfectly with the supernova results. As we've seen, a spatially flat universe requires the total mass/energy density to equal the critical density. With ordinary and dark matter contributing about 30 percent and dark energy contributing about 70 percent, everything hangs together impressively.

A more direct confirmation of the supernova results is the goal of the SuperNova/Acceleration Probe (SNAP). Proposed by scientists at the Lawrence Berkeley Laboratory, SNAP would be a satellite-borne orbiting telescope with the capacity to observe and measure more than twenty times the number of supernovae studied so far. Not only would SNAP be able to confirm the earlier result that 70 percent of the universe is dark energy, but it should also be able to determine the nature of the dark energy more precisely.

You see, although I have described the dark energy as being a version of Einstein's cosmological constant—a constant, unchanging energy that pushes space to expand—there is a closely related but alternative possibility. Remember from our discussion of inflationary cosmology (and the jumping frog) that a field whose value is perched above its lowest energy configuration can act like a cosmological constant, driving an accelerated expansion of space, but will typically do so only for a short time. Sooner or later, the field will find its way to the bottom of its potential energy bowl, and the outward push will disappear. In inflationary cosmology, this happens in a tiny fraction of a second. But by introducing a new field and by carefully choosing its potential energy shape, physicists have found ways for the accelerated expansion to be far milder in its outward push but to last far longer—for the field to drive a comparatively slow and steady accelerated phase of spatial expansion that lasts not for a fraction of a second, but for billions of years, as the field slowly rolls to the lowest energy value. This raises the possibility that, right now, we may be experiencing an extremely gentle version of the inflationary burst believed to have happened during the universe's earliest moments.

The difference between a true cosmological constant and the latter possibility, known as
quintessence,
is of minimal importance today, but has a profound effect on the long-term future of the universe. A cosmological constant is
constant—
it provides a never-ending accelerated expansion, so the universe will expand ever more quickly and become ever more spread out, diluted, and barren. But quintessence provides accelerated expansion that at some point draws to a close, suggesting a far future less bleak and desolate than that following from accelerated expansion that's eternal. By measuring changes in the acceleration of space over long time spans (through observations of supernovae at various distances and hence at various times in the past), SNAP may be able to distinguish between the two possibilities. By determining whether the dark energy truly is a cosmological constant, SNAP will give insight into the long-term fate of the universe.

Space, Time, and Speculation

The journey to discover the nature of space and time has been long and filled with many surprises; no doubt it is still in its early stages. During the last few centuries, we've seen one breakthrough after another radically reshape our conceptions of space and time and reshape them again. The theoretical and experimental proposals we've covered in this book represent our generation's sculpting of these ideas, and will likely be a major part of our scientific legacy. In Chapter 16, we will discuss some of the most recent and speculative advances in an effort to cast light on what might be the next few steps of the journey. But first, in Chapter 15, we will speculate in a different direction.

While there is no set pattern to scientific discovery, history shows that deep understanding is often the first step toward technological control. Understanding of the electromagnetic force in the 1800s ultimately led to the telegraph, radio, and television. With that knowledge, in conjunction with subsequent understanding of quantum mechanics, we were able to develop computers, lasers, and electronic gadgets too numerous to mention. Understanding of the nuclear forces led to dangerous mastery over the most powerful weapons the world has ever known, and to the development of technologies that might one day meet all the world's energy needs with nothing but vats of salt water. Could our ever deepening understanding of space and time be the first step in a similar pattern of discovery and technological development? Will we one day be masters of space and time and do things that for now are only part of science fiction?

No one knows. But let's see how far we've gotten and what it might take to succeed.

15 - Teleporters and Time Machines

TRAVELING THROUGH SPACE AND TIME

Perhaps I just lacked imagination back in the 1960s, but what really struck me as unbelievable was the computer on board the
Enter
prise
. My grade-school sensibilities granted poetic license to warp drive and to a universe populated by aliens fluent in English. But a machine that could—on demand—immediately display a picture of any historical figure who ever lived, give technical specifications for any piece of equipment ever built, or provide access to any book ever written?
That
strained my ability to suspend disbelief. In the late 1960s, this preteen was certain that there'd never be a way to gather, store, and give ready access to such a wealth of information. And yet, less than half a century later, I can sit here in my kitchen with laptop, wireless Internet connection, and voice recognition software and play Kirk, thumbing through a vast storehouse of knowledge—from the pivotal to the puerile—without lifting a finger. True, the speed and efficiency of computers depicted in the twenty-third-century world of
Star Trek
is still enviable, but it's easy to envisage that when that era arrives, our technology will have exceeded the imagined expectations.

This example is but one of many that have made a cliché of science fiction's ability to presage the future. But what of the most tantalizing of all plot devices—the one in which someone enters a chamber, flips a switch, and is transported to a faraway place or a different time? Is it possible we will one day break free from the meager spatial expanse and temporal epoch to which we have been so far confined and explore the farthest reaches of space and time? Or will this distinction between science fiction and reality remain forever sharply drawn? Having already been exposed to my childhood failure to anticipate the information revolution, you might question my ability to divine future technological breakthroughs. So, rather than speculating on the likelihood of what may be, in this chapter I'll describe how far we've actually gone, in both theory and practice, toward realizing teleporters and time machines, and what it would take to go further and attain control over space and time.

Teleportation in a Quantum World

In conventional science fiction depictions, a
teleporter
(or, in
Star Trek
lingo, a
transporter
) scans an object to determine its detailed composition and sends the information to a distant location, where the object is reconstituted. Whether the object itself is "dematerialized," its atoms and molecules being sent along with the blueprint for putting them back together, or whether atoms and molecules located at the receiving end are used to build an exact replica of the object, varies from one fictional incarnation to another. As we'll see, the scientific approach to teleportation developed over the last decade is closer in spirit to the latter category, and this raises two essential questions. The first is a standard but thorny philosophical conundrum: When, if ever, should an exact replica be identified, called, considered, or treated as if it were the original? The second is the question of whether it's possible, even in principle, to examine an object and determine its composition with complete accuracy so that we can draw up a perfect blueprint with which to reconstitute it.

In a universe governed by the laws of classical physics, the answer to the second question would be yes. In principle, the attributes of every particle making up an object—each particle's identity, position, velocity, and so on—could be measured with total precision, transmitted to a distant location, and used as an instruction manual for recreating the object. Doing this for an object composed of more than just a handful of elementary particles would be laughably beyond reach, but in a classical universe, the obstacle would be complexity, not physics.

In a universe governed by the laws of quantum physics—our universe—the situation is far more subtle. We've learned that the act of measurement coaxes one of the myriad potential attributes of an object to snap out of the quantum haze and take on a definite value. When we observe a particle, for example, the definite features we see do not generally reflect the fuzzy quantum mixture of attributes it had a moment before we looked.
1
Thus, if we want to replicate an object, we face a quantum Catch-22. To replicate we must observe, so we know what to replicate. But the act of observation causes change, so if we replicate what we see, we will not replicate what was there before we looked. This suggests that teleportation in a quantum universe is unattainable, not merely because of practical limitations arising from complexity, but because of fundamental limitations inherent in quantum physics. Nevertheless, as we'll see in the next section, in the early 1990s an international team of physicists found an ingenious way to circumvent this conclusion.

As for the first question, regarding the relationship between replica and original, quantum physics gives an answer that's both precise and encouraging. According to quantum mechanics, every electron in the universe is identical to every other, in that they all have exactly the same mass, exactly the same electric charge, exactly the same weak and strong nuclear force properties, and exactly the same total spin. Moreover, our well-tested quantum mechanical description says that these
exhaust
the attributes that an electron can possess; electrons are all identical with regard to these properties, and there are no other properties to consider. In the same sense, every up-quark is the same as every other, every down-quark is the same as every other, every photon is the same as every other, and so on for all other particle species. As recognized by quantum practitioners many decades ago, particles may be thought of as the smallest possible packets of a field (e.g., photons are the smallest packets of the electromagnetic field), and quantum physics shows that such smallest constituents of the same field are always identical. (Or, in the framework of string theory, particles of the same species have identical properties because they are identical vibrations of a single species of string.)

What can differ between two particles of the same species are the probabilities that they are located at various positions, the probabilities that their spins are pointing in particular directions, and the probabilities that they have particular velocities and energies. Or, as physicists say more succinctly, the two particles can be in different
quantum states.
But if two particles of the same species are in the same quantum state—except, possibly, for one particle having a high likelihood of being
here
while the other particle has a high likelihood of being over
there—
the laws of quantum mechanics ensure that they are indistinguishable, not just in practice but in principle. They are perfect twins. If someone were to exchange the particles' positions (more precisely, exchange the two particles' probabilities of being located at any given position), there'd be absolutely no way to tell.

Thus, if we imagine starting with a particle located here,
40
and somehow put another particle of the same species into exactly the same quantum state (same probabilities for spin orientation, energy, and so on) at some distant location, the resulting particle would be indistinguishable from the original and the process would rightly be called quantum teleportation. Of course, were the original particle to survive the process intact, you might be tempted to call the process quantum cloning or, perhaps, quantum faxing. But as we'll see, the scientific realization of these ideas does not preserve the original particle—it is unavoidably modified during the teleportation process—so we won't be faced with this taxonomic dilemma.

A more pressing concern, and one that philosophers have considered closely in various forms, is whether what's true for an individual particle is true for an agglomeration. If you were able to teleport from one location to another every single particle that makes up your DeLorean, ensuring that the quantum state of each, including its relationship to all others, was reproduced with 100% fidelity, would you have succeeded in teleporting the vehicle? Although we have no empirical evidence to guide us, the theoretical case in support of having teleported the car is strong. Atomic and molecular arrangements determine how an object looks and feels, sounds and smells, and even tastes, so the resulting vehicle should be identical to the original DeLorean—bumps, nicks, squeaky left wing-door, musty smell from the family dog, all of it—and the car should take a sharp turn and respond to flooring the gas pedal exactly as the original did. The question of whether the vehicle actually is the original or, instead, is an exact duplicate, is of no concern. If you'd asked United Quantum Van Lines to ship your car by boat from New York to London but, unbeknownst to you, they teleported it in the manner described, you could never know the difference—even in principle.

But what if the moving company did the same to your cat, or, having sated your appetite for airplane gastronomy, what if you decided on teleportation for your own transatlantic travel? Would the cat or person who steps out of the receiving chamber be the same as the one who stepped into the teleporter? Personally, I think so. Again, since we have no relevant data, the best that I or anyone can do is speculate. But to my way of thinking, a living being whose constituent atoms and molecules are in exactly the same quantum state as mine
is
me. Even if the "original" me still existed after the "copy" had been made, I (we) would say without hesitation that each was me. We'd be of the same mind—literally—in asserting that neither would have priority over the other. Thoughts, memories, emotions, and judgments have a physical basis in the human body's atomic and molecular properties; an identical quantum state of these elementary constituents should entail an identical conscious being. As time went by, our experiences would cause us to differentiate, but I truly believe that henceforth there'd be two of me, not an original that was somehow "really" me and a copy that somehow wasn't.

In fact, I'm willing to be a bit looser. Our physical composition goes through numerous transformations all the time—some minor, some drastic—but we remain the same person. From the Häagen-Dazs that inundates the bloodstream with fat and sugar, to the MRI that flips the spin axes of various atomic nuclei in the brain, to heart transplants and liposuction, to the trillion atoms in the average human body that are replaced every millionth of a second, we undergo constant change, yet our personal identity remains unaffected. So, even if a teleported being did not match my physical state with perfect accuracy, it could very well be fully indistinguishable from me. In my book, it could very well
be
me.

Certainly, if you believe that there is more to life, and conscious life in particular, than its physical makeup, your standards for successful teleportation will be more stringent than mine. This tricky issue—to what extent is our personal identity tied to our physical being?—has been debated for years in a variety of guises without being answered to everyone's satisfaction. While I believe identity all resides in the physical, others disagree, and no one can claim to have the definitive answer.

But irrespective of your point of view on the hypothetical question of teleporting a living being, scientists have now established that, through the wonders of quantum mechanics,
individual particles can be—and
have been—teleported.

Let's see how.

BOOK: The Fabric of the Cosmos: Space, Time, and the Texture of Reality
2.02Mb size Format: txt, pdf, ePub
ads

Other books

The Gilded Fan (Choc Lit) by Courtenay, Christina
DarykCraving by Denise A. Agnew
Men Of Flesh And Blood by Emilia Clark
Leap by Jodi Lundgren
The Blonde of the Joke by Bennett Madison
Tomy and the Planet of Lies by Erich von Daniken
Glass Slipper by Abigail Barnette