Read The Fabric of the Cosmos: Space, Time, and the Texture of Reality Online

Authors: Brian Greene

Tags: #Science, #Cosmology, #Popular works, #Astronomy, #Physics, #Universe

The Fabric of the Cosmos: Space, Time, and the Texture of Reality (63 page)

BOOK: The Fabric of the Cosmos: Space, Time, and the Texture of Reality
3.92Mb size Format: txt, pdf, ePub
ads
Inner and Outer Space

Speculating about the future of science is an entertaining and constructive exercise. It places our current undertakings in a broader context, and emphasizes the overarching goals toward which we are slowly and deliberately working. But when such speculation turns to the future of spacetime itself, it takes on an almost mystical quality: we're considering the fate of the very things that dominate our sense of reality. Again, there is no question that regardless of future discoveries, space and time will continue to frame our individual experience; space and time, as far as everyday life goes, are here to stay. What will continue to change, and likely change drastically, is our understanding of the framework they provide— the arena, that is, of experiential reality. After centuries of thought, we still can only portray space and time as the most familiar of strangers. They unabashedly wend their way through our lives, but adroitly conceal their fundamental makeup from the very perceptions they so fully inform and influence.

Over the last century, we've become intimately acquainted with some previously hidden features of space and time through Einstein's two theories of relativity and through quantum mechanics. The slowing of time, the relativity of simultaneity, alternative slicings of spacetime, gravity as the warping and curving of space and time, the probabilistic nature of reality, and long-range quantum entanglement were not on the list of things that even the best of the world's nineteenth-century physicists would have expected to find just around the corner. And yet there they were, as attested to by both experimental results and theoretical explanations.

In our age, we've come upon our own panoply of unexpected ideas: Dark matter and dark energy that appear to be, far and away, the dominant constituents of the universe. Gravitational waves—ripples in the fabric of spacetime—which were predicted by Einstein's general relativity and may one day allow us to peek farther back in time than ever before. A Higgs ocean, which permeates all of space and which, if confirmed, will help us to understand how particles acquire mass. Inflationary expansion, which may explain the shape of the cosmos, resolve the puzzle of why it's so uniform on large scales, and set the direction to time's arrow. String theory, which posits loops and snippets of energy in place of point particles and promises a bold version of Einstein's dream in which all particles and all forces are combined into a single theory. Extra space dimensions, emerging from the mathematics of string theory, and possibly detectable in accelerator experiments during the next decade. A braneworld, in which our three space dimensions may be but one universe among many, floating in a higher-dimensional spacetime. And perhaps even emergent spacetime, in which the very fabric of space and time is composed of more fundamental spaceless and timeless entities.

During the next decade, ever more powerful accelerators will provide much-needed experimental input, and many physicists are confident that data gathered from the highly energetic collisions that are planned will confirm a number of these pivotal theoretical constructs. I share this enthusiasm and eagerly await the results. Until our theories make contact with observable, testable phenomena, they remain in limbo—they remain promising collections of ideas that may or may not have relevance for the real world. The new accelerators will advance the overlap between theory and experiment substantially, and, we physicists hope, will usher many of these ideas into the realm of established science.

But there is another approach that, while more of a long shot, fills me with incomparable wonderment. In Chapter 11 we discussed how the effects of tiny quantum jitters can be seen in any clear night sky since they're stretched enormously by cosmic expansion, resulting in clumps that seed the formation of stars and galaxies. (Recall the analogy of tiny scribbles, drawn on a balloon, that are stretched across its surface when the balloon is inflated.) This realization demonstrably gives access to quantum physics through astronomical observations. Perhaps it can be pushed even further. Perhaps cosmic expansion can stretch the imprints of even shorter-scale processes or features—the physics of strings, or quantum gravity more generally, or the atomized structure of ultramicroscopic spacetime itself—and spread their influence, in some subtle but observable manner, across the heavens. Maybe, that is, the universe has already drawn out the microscopic fibers of the fabric of the cosmos and unfurled them clear across the sky, and all we need do is learn how to recognize the pattern.

Assessing cutting-edge proposals for deep physical laws may well require the ferocious might of particle accelerators able to re-create violent conditions unseen since moments after the big bang. But for me, there would be nothing more poetic, no outcome more graceful, no unification more complete, than for us to confirm our theories of the ultrasmall—our theories about the ultramicroscopic makeup of space, time, and matter—by turning our most powerful telescopes skyward and gazing silently at the stars.

Endnotes

1
The terms
centrifugal
and
centripetal
force are sometimes used when describing spinning motion. But they are merely labels. Our intent is to understand why spinning motion gives rise to force.

2
There is debate concerning Mach's precise views on the material that follows. Some of his writings are a bit ambiguous and some of the ideas attributed to him arose from subsequent interpretations of his work. Since he seems to have been aware of these interpretations and never offered corrections, some have suggested that he agreed with their conclusions. But historical accuracy might be better served if every time I write "Mach argued" or "Mach's ideas," you read it to mean "the prevailing interpretation of an approach initiated by Mach."

3
While I like human examples because they make an immediate connection between the physics we're discussing and innate sensations, a drawback is our ability to move, volitionally, one part of our body relative to another—in effect, to use one part of our body as the benchmark for another part's motion (like someone who spins one of his arms relative to his head). I emphasize
uniform
spinning motion—spinning motion in which every part of the body spins together—to avoid such irrelevant complications. So, when I talk about your body's spinning, imagine that, like Newton's two rocks tied by a rope or a skater in the final moments of an Olympic routine, every part of your body spins at the same rate as every other.

4
Like the pages in any flip book, the pages in Figure 3.3 only show representative moments of time. This may suggest to you the interesting question of whether time is discrete or infinitely divisible. We'll come back to that question later, but for now imagine that time is infinitely divisible, so our flip book really should have an infinite number of pages interpolating between those shown.

5
It's easier to picture warped space, but because of their intimate connection, time is also warped by matter and energy. And just as a warp in space means that space is stretched or compressed, as in Figure 3.10, a warp in time means that time is stretched or compressed. That is, clocks experiencing different gravitational pulls—like one on the sun and another in deep, empty space—tick off time at different rates. In fact, it turns out that the warping of space caused by ordinary bodies like the earth and sun (as opposed to black holes) is far less pronounced than the warping they inflict on time.
15

6
In special relativity—the special case of general relativity in which the gravitational field is zero—this idea applies unchanged: a zero gravitational field is still a field, one that can be measured and changed, and hence provides a something relative to which acceleration can be defined.

7
To avoid linguistic complications, I'm describing the electron spins as perfectly correlated, even though the more conventional description is one in which they're perfectly
anti
correlated: whatever result one detector finds, the other will find the opposite. To compare with the conventional description, imagine that I've interchanged all the clockwise and counterclockwise labels on one of the detectors.

8
Many researchers, including me, believe that Bell's argument and Aspect's experiment establish convincingly that the observed correlations between widely separated particles cannot be explained by Scully-type reasoning—reasoning that attributes the correlations to nothing more surprising than the particles' having acquired definite, correlated properties when they were (previously) together. Others have sought to evade or lessen the stunning nonlocality conclusion to which this has led us. I don't share their skepticism, but some works for general readers that discuss some of these alternatives are cited in the note section.15

9
Pick any point in the loaf. Draw a slice that includes the point, and which intersects our current now-slice at an angle that is less than 45 degrees. This slice will represent the now-slice
—reality—
of a distant observer who was initially at rest relative to us, like Chewie, but is now moving relative to us at less than the speed of light. By design, this slice includes the (arbitrary) point in the loaf you happened to pick.
4

10
There is an exception to this statement having to do with a certain class of exotic particles. As far as the questions discussed in this chapter are concerned, I consider this likely to be of little relevance and so won't mention this qualification further. If you are interested, it is briefly discussed in note 2.

11
Note that time-reversal symmetry is not about time itself being reversed or "running" backward. Instead, as we've described, time-reversal symmetry is concerned with whether events that happen
in
time, in one particular temporal order, can also happen in the reverse order. A more appropriate phrase might be
event reversal
or
process reversal
or
event
order reversal,
but we'll stick with the conventional term.

12
Entropy is another example in which terminology complicates ideas. Don't worry if you have to remind yourself repeatedly that
low
entropy means
high
order and that
high
entropy means
low
order (equivalently, high disorder). I often have to.

13
Remember, on pages 152-53 we showed the huge difference between the number of ordered and disordered configurations for a mere 693 double-sided sheets of paper. We are now discussing the behavior of roughly 10
24
H
2
O molecules, so the difference between the number of ordered and disordered configurations is breathtakingly monumental. Moreover, the same reasoning holds for all other atoms and molecules within you and within the environment (brains, security cameras, air molecules, and so on). Namely, in the standard explanation in which you can trust your memories, not only would the partially melted ice cubes have begun, at 10 p.m., in a more ordered—less likely—state, but so would everything else: when a video camera records a sequence of events, there is a net increase in entropy (from the heat and noise released by the recording process); similarly, when a brain records a memory, although we understand the microscopic details with less accuracy, there is a net increase in entropy (the brain may gain order but as with any order-producing process, if we take account of heat generated, there is a net increase in entropy). Thus, if we compare the total entropy in the bar between 10 p.m. and 10:30 p.m. in the two scenarios—one in which you trust your memories, and the other in which things spontaneously arrange themselves from an initial state of disorder to be consistent with what you see, now, at 10:30 p.m.—there is an enormous entropy difference. The latter scenario, every step of the way, has
hugely
more entropy than the former scenario, and so, from the standpoint of probability, is hugely more likely.

14
A closely related point is that should we convince ourselves that the world we see right now just coalesced out of total disorder, the exact same reasoning—invoked anytime later—would require us to abandon our current belief and, instead, attribute the ordered world to a yet more recent fluctuation. Thus, in this way of thinking, every next moment invalidates the beliefs held in each previous moment, a distinctly unconvincing way of explaining the cosmos.

15
That is, a black hole of a given size contains more entropy than
anything
else of the same size.

16
Even though Feynman's sum over histories approach might seem to make the particle aspect prominent, it is just a particular interpretation of probability
waves
(since it involves many histories for a single particle, each making its own probabilistic contribution), and so is subsumed by the wavelike side of complementarity. When we speak of something behaving like a particle, we will always mean a conventional particle that travels along one and only one trajectory.

17
If you find this section tough going, you can safely move on to the next section without loss of continuity. But I encourage you to try to get through it, as the results are truly stupendous.

18
Quantum mechanics, rightly, has a reputation as being anything but smooth and gradual; rather, as we will see explicitly in later chapters, it reveals a turbulent and jittery microcosmos. The origin of this jitteriness is the probabilistic nature of the wavefunction—even though things can be one way at one moment, there is a probability that they will be significantly different a moment later—
not
an ever-present jittery quality of the wavefunction itself.

BOOK: The Fabric of the Cosmos: Space, Time, and the Texture of Reality
3.92Mb size Format: txt, pdf, ePub
ads

Other books

The Time Sphere by A.E. Albert
Tinkerbell on Walkabout by Maya Kaathryn Bohnhoff
Valley of Decision by Stanley Middleton
Cover Her Face by P. D. James
The Coke Machine by Michael Blanding
The Warlords Revenge by Alyssa Morgan