Read The Fabric of the Cosmos: Space, Time, and the Texture of Reality Online

Authors: Brian Greene

Tags: #Science, #Cosmology, #Popular works, #Astronomy, #Physics, #Universe

The Fabric of the Cosmos: Space, Time, and the Texture of Reality (60 page)

BOOK: The Fabric of the Cosmos: Space, Time, and the Texture of Reality
3.51Mb size Format: txt, pdf, ePub
ads
Cosmic Rubbernecking

In thinking about time travel, Hawking has raised an interesting point. Why, he asks, if time travel is possible, haven't we been inundated with visitors from the future? Well, you might answer, maybe we have. And you might go further and say we've put so many time travelers in locked wards that most of the others don't dare identify themselves. Of course, Hawking is half joking, and so am I, but he does raise a serious question. If you believe, as I do, that we have not been visited from the future, is that tantamount to believing time travel impossible? Surely, if people succeed in building time machines in the future, some historian is bound to get a grant to study, up close and personal, the building of the first atomic bomb, or the first voyage to the moon, or the first foray into reality television. So, if we believe no one has visited us from the future, perhaps we are implicitly saying that we believe no such time machine will ever be built.

Actually, though, this is not a necessary conclusion.
The time
machines that have thus far been proposed do not allow travel to a time
prior to the construction of the first time machine itself.
For the wormhole time machine, this is easy to see by examining Figure 15.5. Although there is a time difference between the wormhole mouths, and although that difference allows travel forward and backward in time, you can't reach a time before the time difference was established. The wormhole itself does not exist on the far left of the spacetime loaf, so there is no way you can use it to get there. Thus, if the first time machine is built, say, 10,000 years from now,
that
moment will no doubt attract many time-traveling tourists, but all previous times, such as ours, will remain inaccessible.

I find it curious and compelling that our current understanding of nature's laws not only suggests how to avoid the seeming paradoxes of time travel but also offers proposals for how time travel might actually be accomplished. Don't get me wrong: I count myself among the sober physicists who feel intuitively that we will one day rule out time travel to the past. But until there's definitive proof, I think it justified and appropriate to keep an open mind. At the very least, researchers focusing on these issues are substantially deepening our understanding of space and time in extreme circumstances. At the very best, they may be taking the first critical steps toward integrating us into the spacetime superhighway. After all, every moment that goes by without our having succeeded in building a time machine is a moment that will be forever beyond our reach and the reach of all who follow.

16 - The Future of an Allusion

PROSPECTS FOR SPACE AND TIME

Physicists spend a large part of their lives in a state of confusion. It's an occupational hazard. To excel in physics is to embrace doubt while walking the winding road to clarity. The tantalizing discomfort of perplexity is what inspires otherwise ordinary men and women to extraordinary feats of ingenuity and creativity; nothing quite focuses the mind like dissonant details awaiting harmonious resolution. But en route to explanation—during their search for new frameworks to address outstanding questions—theorists must tread with considered step through the jungle of bewilderment, guided mostly by hunches, inklings, clues, and calculations. And as the majority of researchers have a tendency to cover their tracks, discoveries often bear little evidence of the arduous terrain that's been covered. But don't lose sight of the fact that nothing comes easily. Nature does not give up her secrets lightly.

In this book we've looked at numerous chapters in the story of our species' attempt to understand space and time. And although we have encountered some deep and astonishing insights, we've yet to reach that ultimate eureka moment when all confusion abates and total clarity prevails. We are, most definitely, still wandering in the jungle. So, where from here? What is the next chapter in spacetime's story? Of course, no one knows for sure. But in recent years a number of clues have come to light, and although they've yet to be integrated into a coherent picture, many physicists believe they are hinting at the next big upheaval in our understanding of the cosmos. In due course, space and time as currently conceived may be recognized as mere allusions to more subtle, more profound, and more fundamental principles underlying physical reality. In the final chapter of this account, let's consider some of these clues and catch a glimpse of where we may be headed in our continuing quest to grasp the fabric of the cosmos.

Are Space and Time Fundamental Concepts?

The German philosopher Immanuel Kant suggested that it would be not merely difficult to do away with space and time when thinking about and describing the universe, it would be downright impossible. Frankly, I can see where Kant was coming from. Whenever I sit, close my eyes, and try to think about things while somehow not depicting them as occupying space or experiencing the passage of time, I fall short. Way short. Space, through context, or time, through change, always manages to seep in. Ironically, the closest I come to ridding my thoughts of a direct spacetime association is when I'm immersed in a mathematical calculation (often having to do with spacetime!), because the nature of the exercise seems able to engulf my thoughts, if only momentarily, in an abstract setting that seems devoid of space and time. But the thoughts themselves and the body in which they take place are, all the same, very much part of familiar space and time. Truly eluding space and time makes escaping your shadow a cakewalk.

Nevertheless, many of today's leading physicists suspect that space and time, although pervasive, may not be truly fundamental. Just as the hardness of a cannonball emerges from the collective properties of its atoms, and just as the smell of a rose emerges from the collective properties of its molecules, and just as the swiftness of a cheetah emerges from the collective properties of its muscles, nerves, and bones, so too, the properties of space and time—our preoccupation for much of this book— may also emerge from the collective behavior of some other, more fundamental constituents, which we've yet to identify.

Physicists sometimes sum up this possibility by saying that spacetime may be an illusion—a provocative depiction, but one whose meaning requires proper interpretation. After all, if you were to be hit by a speeding cannonball, or inhale the alluring fragrance of a rose, or catch sight of a blisteringly fast cheetah, you wouldn't deny their existence simply because each is composed of finer, more basic entities. To the contrary, I think most of us would agree that these agglomerations of matter exist, and moreover, that there is much to be learned from studying how their familiar characteristics emerge from their atomic constituents. But because they are composites, what we wouldn't try to do is build a theory of the universe based on cannonballs, roses, or cheetahs. Similarly, if space and time turn out to be composite entities, it wouldn't mean that their familiar manifestations, from Newton's bucket to Einstein's gravity, are illusory; there is little doubt that space and time will retain their all-embracing positions in experiential reality, regardless of future developments in our understanding. Instead, composite spacetime would mean that an even more elemental description of the universe—one that is spaceless and timeless—has yet to be discovered. The illusion, then, would be one of our own making: the erroneous belief that the deepest understanding of the cosmos would bring space and time into the sharpest possible focus. Just as the hardness of a cannonball, the smell of the rose, and the speed of the cheetah disappear when you examine matter at the atomic and subatomic level, space and time may similarly dissolve when scrutinized with the most fundamental formulation of nature's laws.

That spacetime may not be among the fundamental cosmic ingredients may strike you as somewhat far-fetched. And you may well be right. But rumors of spacetime's impending departure from deep physical law are not born of zany theorizing. Instead, this idea is strongly suggested by a number of well-reasoned considerations. Let's take a look at some of the most prominent.

Quantum Averaging

In Chapter 12 we discussed how the fabric of space, much like everything else in our quantum universe, is subject to the jitters of quantum uncertainty. It is these fluctuations, you'll recall, that run roughshod over point-particle theories, preventing them from providing a sensible quantum theory of gravity. By replacing point particles with loops and snippets, string theory spreads out the fluctuations—substantially reducing their magnitude—and this is how it yields a successful unification of quantum mechanics and general relativity. Nevertheless, the diminished spacetime fluctuations certainly still exist (as illustrated in the next-to-last level of magnification in Figure 12.2), and within them we can find important clues regarding the fate of spacetime.

First, we learn that the familiar space and time that suffuse our thoughts and support our equations emerge from a kind of averaging process. Think of the pixelated image you see when your face is a few inches from a television screen. This image is very different from what you see at a more comfortable distance, because once you can no longer resolve individual pixels, your eyes combine them into an average that looks smooth. But notice that it's only through the averaging process that the pixels produce a familiar, continuous image. In a similar vein, the microscopic structure of spacetime is riddled with random undulations, but we aren't directly aware of them because we lack the ability to resolve spacetime on such minute scales. Instead, our eyes, and even our most powerful equipment, combine the undulations into an average, much like what happens with television pixels. Because the undulations are random, there are typically as many "up" undulations in a small region as there are "down," so when averaged they tend to cancel out, yielding a placid spacetime. But, as in the television analogy,
it's only because of the
averaging process that a smooth and tranquil form for spacetime emerges.

Quantum averaging provides a down-to-earth interpretation of the assertion that familiar spacetime may be illusory. Averages are useful for many purposes but, by design, they do not provide a sharp picture of underlying details. Although the average family in the U.S. has 2.2 children, you'd be in a bind were I to ask to visit such a family. And although the national average price for a gallon of milk is $2.783, you're unlikely to find a store selling it for exactly this price. So, too, familiar spacetime, itself the result of an averaging process, may not describe the details of something we'd want to call fundamental. Space and time may only be approximate, collective conceptions, extremely useful in analyzing the universe on all but ultramicroscopic scales, yet as illusory as a family with 2.2 children.

A second and related insight is that the increasingly intense quantum jitters that arise on decreasing scales suggest that the notion of being able to divide distances or durations into ever smaller units likely comes to an end at around the Planck length (10
-33
centimeters) and Planck time (10
-43
seconds). We encountered this idea in Chapter 12, where we emphasized that, although the notion is thoroughly at odds with our usual experiences of space and time, it is not particularly surprising that a property relevant to the everyday fails to survive when pushed into the micro-realm. And since the arbitrary divisibility of space and time is one of their most familiar everyday properties, the inapplicability of this concept on ultrasmall scales gives another hint that there is something else lurking in the microdepths—something that might be called the bare-bones substrate of spacetime—the entity to which the familiar notion of spacetime alludes. We expect that this
ur
-ingredient, this most elemental spacetime stuff, does not allow dissection into ever smaller pieces because of the violent fluctuations that would ultimately be encountered, and hence is quite unlike the large-scale spacetime we directly experience. It seems likely, therefore, that the appearance of the fundamental spacetime constituents—whatever they may be—is altered significantly through the averaging process by which they yield the spacetime of common experience.

Thus, looking for familiar spacetime in the deepest laws of nature may be like trying to take in Beethoven's Ninth Symphony solely note by single note or one of Monet's haystack paintings solely brushstroke by single brushstroke. Like these masterworks of human expression, nature's spacetime whole may be so different from its parts that nothing resembling it exists at the most fundamental level.

Geometry in Translation

Another consideration, one physicists call
geometrical duality,
also suggests that spacetime may not be fundamental, but suggests it from a very different viewpoint. Its description is a little more technical than quantum averaging, so feel free to go into skim mode if at any point this section gets too heavy. But because many researchers consider this material to be among string theory's most emblematic features, it's worth trying to get the gist of the ideas.

In Chapter 13 we saw how the five supposedly distinct string theories are actually different translations of one and the same theory. Among other things, we emphasized that this is a powerful realization because, when translated, supremely difficult questions sometimes become far simpler to answer. But there is a feature of the translation dictionary unifying the five theories that I've so far neglected to mention. Just as a question's degree of difficulty can be changed radically by the translation from one string formulation to another, so, too, can the description of the geometrical form of spacetime. Here's what I mean.

Because string theory requires more than the three space dimensions and one time dimension of common experience, we were motivated in Chapters 12 and 13 to take up the question of where the extra dimensions might be hiding. The answer we found is that they may be curled up into a size that, so far, has eluded detection because it's smaller than we are able to probe experimentally. We also found that physics in our familiar big dimensions is dependent on the precise size and shape of the extra dimensions because their geometrical properties affect the vibrational patterns strings can execute. Good. Now for the part I left out.

The dictionary that translates questions posed in one string theory into different questions posed in another string theory
also translates the
geometry of the extra dimensions in the first theory into a different extra-dimensionalgeometry in the second theory.
If, for example, you are studying the physical implications of, say, the Type IIA string theory with extra dimensions curled up into a particular size and shape, then every conclusion you reach can, at least in principle, be deduced by considering appropriately translated questions in, say, the Type IIB string theory. But the dictionary for carrying out the translation
demands
that the extra dimensions in the Type IIB string theory be curled up into a precise geometrical form that depends on
—but
generally differs from—
the form given by the Type IIA theory. In short, a given string theory with curled-up dimensions in one geometrical form is equivalent to—is a translation of— another string theory with curled-up dimensions in a
different
geometrical form.

And the differences in spacetime geometry need not be minor. For example, if one of the extra dimensions of, say, the Type IIA string theory should be curled up into a circle, as in Figure 12.7, the translation dictionary shows that this is absolutely equivalent to the Type IIB string theory with one of its extra dimensions also curled up into a circle, but one whose radius is
inversely
proportional to the original. If one circle is tiny, the other is big, and vice versa—and yet there is absolutely no way to distinguish between the two geometries. (Expressing lengths as multiples of the Planck length, if one circle has radius
R,
the mathematical dictionary shows that the other circle has radius 1/
R
). You might think that you could easily and immediately distinguish between a big and a small dimension, but in string theory this is not always the case. All observations derive from the interactions of strings, and these two theories, the Type IIA with a big circular dimension and the Type IIB with a small circular dimension, are merely different translations of—different ways of expressing—the same physics. Every observation you describe within one string theory has an alternative and equally viable description within the other string theory, even though the language of each theory and the interpretation it gives may differ. (This is possible because there are two qualitatively different configurations for strings moving on a circular dimension: those in which the string is wrapped around the circle like a rubber band around a tin can, and those in which the string resides on a portion of the circle but does not wrap around it. The former have energies that are
proportional
to the radius of the circle [the larger the radius, the longer the wrapped strings are stretched, so the more energy they embody], while the latter have energies that are
inversely proportional
to the radius [the smaller the radius, the more hemmed in the strings are, so the more energetically they move because of quantum uncertainty]. Notice that if we were to replace the original circle by one of
inverted
radius, while also exchanging "wrapped" and "not wrapped" strings, physical energies—and, it turns out, physics more generally—would remain unaffected. This is exactly what the dictionary translating from the Type IIA theory to the Type IIB theory requires, and why two seemingly different geometries—a big and a small circular dimension—can be equivalent.)

A similar idea also holds when circular dimensions are replaced with the more complicated Calabi-Yau shapes introduced in Chapter 12. A given string theory with extra dimensions curled up into a particular Calabi-Yau shape gets translated by the dictionary into a different string theory with extra dimensions curled up into a different Calabi-Yau shape (one that is called the
mirror
or
dual
of the original). In these cases, not only can the sizes of the Calabi-Yaus differ, but so can their shapes, including the number and variety of their holes. But the translation dictionary ensures that they differ in just the right way, so that even though the extra dimensions have different sizes and shapes, the physics following from each theory is absolutely identical. (There are two types of holes in a given Calabi-Yau shape, but it turns out that string vibrational patterns—and hence physical implications—are sensitive only to the
difference
between the number of holes of each type. So if one Calabi-Yau has, say, two holes of the first kind and five of the second, while another Calabi-Yau has five holes of the first kind and two of the second, then even though they differ as geometrical shapes, they can give rise to identical physics.
44
)

From another perspective, then, this bolsters the suspicion that space is not a foundational concept. Someone describing the universe using one of the five string theories would claim that space, including the extra dimensions, has a particular size and shape, while someone else using one of the other string theories would claim that space, including the extra dimensions, has a different size and shape. Because the two observers would simply be using alternative
mathematical
descriptions of the same
physical
universe, it is not that one would be right and the other wrong. They would both be right, even though their conclusions about space— its size and shape—would differ. Note too, that it's not that they would be slicing up spacetime in different, equally valid ways, as in special relativity. These two observers would fail to agree on the overall structure of spacetime itself. And that's the point. If spacetime were really fundamental, most physicists expect that everyone, regardless of perspective—regardless of the language or theory used—would agree on its geometrical properties. But the fact that, at least within string theory, this need not be the case, suggests that spacetime may be a secondary phenomenon.

We are thus led to ask: if the clues described in the last two sections are pointing us in the right direction, and familiar spacetime is but a large-scale manifestation of some more fundamental entity, what is that entity and what are its essential properties? As of today, no one knows. But in the search for answers, researchers have found yet further clues, and the most important have come from thinking about black holes.

BOOK: The Fabric of the Cosmos: Space, Time, and the Texture of Reality
3.51Mb size Format: txt, pdf, ePub
ads

Other books

The Reluctant Lark by Iris Johansen
The Smoke-Scented Girl by Melissa McShane
Viper's Defiant Mate by S. E. Smith
in0 by Unknown
All She Wanted (2) by Nicole Deese
To Serve a King by Donna Russo Morin
The Forlorn Hope by David Drake