Life's Ratchet: How Molecular Machines Extract Order from Chaos (5 page)

BOOK: Life's Ratchet: How Molecular Machines Extract Order from Chaos
9.12Mb size Format: txt, pdf, ePub
ads

Descartes’s philosophical ideas were an important step toward a mechanical view of life. Performing (sometimes gruesome) experiments on animals, he discerned that the body acted like a machine with pumps and pipes. He was one of the first natural philosophers to argue for the investigation of the body from a mechanical perspective, devoid of any mysterious forces. These ideas landed Descartes in hot water with the Catholic Church, despite his being a devout churchgoer. Descartes tried his best to reconcile what he saw in nature with Catholic theology. His solution was to divorce “mind” from the mechanical worldview he espoused. The mind or spirit was to be the realm of the soul and the divine, while the body was pure machine. The soul, which once explained everything, from the growth of plants to the human mind, had now been confined to mind alone. Everything else was matter in motion.

The first modern atomists, after the almost complete suppression of atomism during the Middle Ages, were Isaac Beeckman (1588–1637), a Dutch philosopher and scientist, and Pierre Gassendi (1592–1655), a French Jesuit priest. Beeckman, Descartes’s teacher and friend, was considered one of most educated men of Europe at the time. Gassendi followed Beeckman in arguing for a revival of atomism and strived to make Epicurean atomism palatable for the Catholic Church. Gassendi had a different approach from that of Descartes: Whereas Descartes created
dualism
, the separate realms of matter and soul, Gassendi animated his atoms with the power of God, returning to an animistic view of the universe.
If atoms were responsible for life, the necessary intelligence had to be built into them. And who endowed the atoms with this intelligence? God, of course.

This idea was later adopted by the German philosopher Gottfried Leibniz (1646–1716), who replaced atoms by “monads,” atomic units of thought. Later materialist philosophers, however, would discard God altogether and instead endow atoms with uncreated purpose, an idea that during the Enlightenment, the French philosopher Voltaire (1694–1778) found laughable. According to Voltaire, the idea of some kind of uncreated intelligence inherent in atoms was ridiculous. Wasn’t it simpler to just believe in God? After two thousand years of debate, it seemed that philosophers had not advanced much beyond Aristotle and Democritus.

But this would be unfair: The mechanical worldview, the revival of atomism, and the combination of rational examination and experiment were the foundation for one of the most influential periods in the history of science, the scientific revolution, which lasted from the late sixteenth to the eighteenth century. During this period, modern science was born and natural philosophers began to distinguish science from mysticism. The towering figures of this period were Galileo Galilei (1564–1642) and Isaac Newton (1642–1726). Both Galileo and Newton were atomists and believed in using experiment and reason to find new truths about nature. Newton had a Lucretian idea of how atoms form macroscopic matter; he thought of matter as made of small, hard particles that stick together to make larger particles. This idea explained how materials can break apart, as they break “not in the midst of solid particles, but where those particles are laid together, and only touch in a few points.”

Newton stood at the threshold between Renaissance mysticism and modern science, and much has been made of his interest in alchemy and obscure theological pursuits. Yet his alchemy led him to value experimental approaches and validated his atomism. Newton appeared to know the difference between mysticism and science and kept his alchemy and theology neatly separated from his scientific and mathematical writings. He even went so far as to defend his scientific findings from those who thought that he was advocating new occult forces: “These Principles I consider, not as occult Qualities, supposed to result from the specifick Forms of Things, but as general Laws of Nature, by which the Things themselves
are form’d; their Truth appearing to us by Phænomena, though their Causes be not yet discover’d
.

The mechanical philosophy and the new atomism compelled scientists during the scientific revolution to look ever more closely at the living world, and advances in optics provided new instruments for the search of the “atoms” of nature. The microscope was invented in the late 1500s in the Netherlands by two Dutch spectacle makers, Zacharias Janssen and his son Hans. Improvements to the microscope were completed by Galileo (1609) and Cornelius Drebbel (1619). In 1614, Galileo observed that flies had “fur.” Others observed mites and studied the structure of a fly’s eye. The most famous early book on microscopic observations was Hooke’s
Micrographia
of 1665. Robert Hooke (1635–1703), a master experimenter, used his homebuilt microscope to look at everything from flees to “gravel” in urine. The early microscopists discovered what Hooke called “small machines of nature,” from the legs of flees to single-celled animals. Hooke was the first to see cells in cork. The first animal cells, red blood cells, were discovered shortly thereafter by Antonie Philips van Leeuwenhoek (1632–1723), but neither he nor Hooke realized that these cells were the smallest units of all living beings.

Hooke and his contemporaries discovered that life was a wondrous menagerie of mechanisms, from the smallest “animalcules” to the body of a human. The search for smaller and smaller units continued for over two hundred years, leading to the cell theory in the mid-1800s. For Hooke and his fellow microscopists, the mechanical philosophy compelled them to look carefully at the components of living beings. What they saw confirmed their mechanical view of life. Observing the growth of mold, Hooke noted: “I must conclude, that as far as I have been able to look into the nature of this Primary kind of life and vegetation, I cannot find the least probable argument to perswade me there is any other concurrent cause then such as is purely Mechanical.”

L’homme machine
 

Some people just don’t know when to shut up.

Julien Offray de La Mettrie (1709–1751), Brittany native, medical doctor, and radical Enlightenment philosopher, certainly didn’t (
Figure 1.2
).
When his first venture into philosophy,
A Natural History of the Soul
(1745), was burned in Paris for its impiety, he followed with an attack on the less-than-competent physicians of France. Having thoroughly upset both the medical and the religious establishments, he fled to Holland. Then, in 1747, he continued his attacks with
The Vengeful Faculty
, against the physicians, and
Man a Machine
(
L’homme machine
), against the priests. Holland was no longer safe, and La Mettrie found refuge at the court of Frederick the Great in Berlin. The Prussian king loved the French and the Enlightenment, and you couldn’t be more Enlightenment than La Mettrie.

 

FIGURE 1.2.
Julien Offray de La Mettrie. Another laughing materialist philosopher, although unlike Democritus, he has no beard.

 

What had La Mettrie written in
L’homme machine
that so upset his contemporaries?

After receiving his medical doctorate from the University of Rheims, La Mettrie had served as medical officer to the French Guards and participated in a number of bloody battles. Through this experience, he developed a profound distaste for the slaughter of war and saw what savagery and injury could do to the human mind. He came to realize that reason and emotion, supposedly part of the soul, could be thoroughly altered by injury. Didn’t this clearly show that Descartes’s last refuge of soul—the mind—could ultimately be explained by pure mechanism? No wonder La Mettrie’s more religious contemporaries were displeased.

Because of his provocative writings, La Mettrie is sometimes seen as the bad boy of the Enlightenment. The rumor that he died while overeating
expensive pheasant pâté did not help his reputation (although it seems likely he died of food poisoning). However, under the combative veneer of his writing, there was a thoughtful philosopher and one of the most uncompromising representatives of the mechanical philosophy.

La Mettrie was a better provocateur and philosopher than scientist. But we can hardly fault him for that: While his explanations of procreation or “irritability” (see next paragraph) seem to us naive or laughable, he based them on what little was known about human physiology at a time when alchemical and ancient Greek ideas were still common. But his philosophy did not depend on such details.

At the heart of his most famous work,
L’homme machine
, were two observations: First, the functions of body and mind could be greatly altered by physical influences and therefore could not be independent of them. Second, living tissue, such as muscle, could move on its own, even when removed from the body. Experiments performed during La Mettrie’s time demonstrated that isolated tissues could move when “irritated.” This so-called irritability indicated to La Mettrie that life possessed “inherent powers of purposive motion.” He put irritability at the center of his arguments, providing a list of ten examples, some quite gruesome, such as the frantic fluttering of headless chickens. In light of these observations, La Mettrie concluded that we cannot divorce the functions of the body or the mind from their physical nature. Instead, the functions must be the
result
of the physical and mechanical makeup.

La Mettrie’s denial of the soul led to his being charged as an atheist (the standard charge for all philosophers who spoke out against Church doctrine). But he was more of a sincere agnostic: “I [do not] question the existence of a supreme being; on the contrary, it seems to me that the greatest degree of probability is in its favor. But that doesn’t prove that one religion must be right, against all the others; it is a theoretical truth that serves very little practical purpose.” For him, metaphysical and theological speculations about the soul served little purpose when a meal could make the “soul” happy and content and when we could see “to what excesses cruel hunger can push us.” La Mettrie, tongue-in-cheek, observed that “one could say at times that the soul is found in our stomach.” Observing that hunger, injury, drugs, and sleep affected people’s minds, he felt certain that the soul was just part of the body, even if he could not
explain in detail how it worked: “It is folly to waste one’s time trying to discover its mechanism. . . . There is no way of discovering how matter comes to move.”

La Mettrie was wrong to state that “there is no way” to discover how organized matter moves, but we can agree with him that a supernatural soul is probably not needed to render us alive, as Aristotle believed, because the soul is so dependent on the physical state of the body. La Mettrie concluded that the “soul’s abilities” clearly depend on the “specific organization of the brain and the whole body.” Therefore, the soul was nothing other than the organization of the body and, as a separate concept, empty. It had taken two thousand years before somebody could freely acknowledge that a soul was not necessary to explain the motions of the body.

La Mettrie’s agnosticism gave him a modern outlook on the methodology of science (although modern scientists are more diplomatic) and a somewhat religious awe of nature governed by necessity. He wondered “why would it be absurd to believe that there exist physical causes for everything that has been made.” Was it not “our absolutely incurable ignorance of these causes that has made us resort to a God?” For him, the answers for the mystery of life and mind lay not in chance, nor in God, but in nature.

La Mettrie’s rejection of chance was very much in the spirit of the pre-Darwinian world. It was difficult to see what role chance could play in the emergence of the organized state of matter we call life. La Mettrie believed that a purely physical explanation of life was possible—but a mechanical explanation had to explain all aspects of life previously explained by religion. When God became an “unnecessary hypothesis,” nature had to fill the gap and produce life and the human race out of necessity. The mechanical philosophy, like other explanations that relied on the fashionable ideas of the day, compared living beings to mechanical contraptions such as clocks.
*
Clocks, when well maintained, leave nothing to chance; they are the epitome of necessity.

For La Mettrie, nature acted on many levels, from the simple to the complex. He opposed artificial barriers to physical explanations and rejected the idea that there was a wall beyond which physics could not tread. The difference between a falling rock and a human mind was not one of different matter or different laws of nature, but one of a tremendous increase in complexity. And even if this complexity prevented us from completely explaining how a human mind works, this failure did not warrant the insertion of soul or God into this gap in our understanding. “Just as, given certain physical laws, it would not be possible for the sea to not have its ebb and flow, the same . . . laws of motion . . . would form eyes which see, ears that hear, nerves that feel, tongues that can or cannot talk depending on their organization; and finally, would fabricate the organ for thought. Nature has made in the human machine another machine, which finds itself capable of retaining ideas and creating new ones . . . it has made, blindly, eyes that can see; it has made without thought, a machine that thinks.”

BOOK: Life's Ratchet: How Molecular Machines Extract Order from Chaos
9.12Mb size Format: txt, pdf, ePub
ads

Other books

LANCEJACK (The Union Series) by Richards, Phillip
These Three Words by Holly Jacobs
A Little Harmless Submission 6 by Melissa Schroeder
Marrying Her Royal Enemy by Jennifer Hayward
Zoli by Colum McCann
A Place to Belong by Joan Lowery Nixon