Pythagorus (14 page)

Read Pythagorus Online

Authors: Kitty Ferguson

Tags: #history, #ancient mathematicians

BOOK: Pythagorus
10.78Mb size Format: txt, pdf, ePub

If Pythagoras discovered or knew the rule, did he prove it? Most historians of mathematics believe that the concept of ‘proof' as later understood was unknown before the Alexandrian Euclid introduced it in his
Elements,
around 300 B.C. The decision that something would ‘be true for every right triangle', for someone living as early as Pythagoras, would probably have been made on grounds other than a Euclidian proof. It would either have been an unsupported assumption or a guess, or a decision made in a scientific rather than a mathematical way – by testing it, as many times and with as many different examples as possible. The idea that mathematical statements should apply generally, though taken for granted today and implied in the Babylonian work, was not usually part of the ancient mind-set before Pythagoras. It is considered to be one of the great contributions of early Greek mathematics and probably a contribution of Pythagoras and his followers. With them, it might have been only an assumption based on their belief in the unity of all being, not something they could demonstrate at all or even thought it necessary to demonstrate.

There are, nevertheless, simple proofs of the theorem that some would like to attribute to the Pythagoreans, and one argument that they used such proofs is that these same thought sequences are good ways to discover the theorem, even if you had no concept of ‘proofs' after the fact. There is a geometry lesson in Plato's
Meno
that some think is traceable to Pythagoras. The clue is that Plato used it to demonstrate the ‘recollection' of what one learned before birth, an idea related to the Pythagorean doctrine of memory of past lives. The triangle in the
Meno
proof is the troublesome isosceles triangle, but the proof sidesteps the problem of incommensurability by using no numbers. It is admittedly difficult to imagine Pythagoreans being satisfied with any ‘truth' that used no numbers. It would have seemed the universe was thumbing its nose at them, with this triangle that provided such a clear and unequivocal demonstration of their rule, and that contained incommensurability. The discussion of Plato's proof fits better in the context of a later chapter. Bronowski, in the book from his television series, showed another well known numberless proof that he believed Pythagoras may have used. This clever proof is in the Appendix.

The right triangle was not the only pitfall in Pythagorean thinking where incommensurability lurked, but it was the most obvious. The scholarly argument about whether the Pythagoreans discovered it, and whether that caused a crisis of faith in the rationality of the universe, rambles on until it resembles that string of digits after the decimal place in an irrational number. However, in truth, an intelligent person thinking along Pythagorean lines and dealing with right triangles could hardly have missed discovering incommensurability. But only someone who reverenced numbers and the rationality of the universe would have been deeply troubled. Some have thought that Pythagoras and his followers reacted by retreating to a geometry without numbers – that what had early been an ‘arithmetised geometry' was reformulated in a nonarithmetical way, and this carried over into Euclid. In spite of the passage in Plato's
Meno
, and the suggestion that it reflected Pythagoras' proof of his theorem, nothing could seem more blatantly un-Pythagorean than a retreat from numbers!
15

Porphyry would have been pleased to learn that the earlier Mesopotamians knew about right triangles, the triples, and the theorem. His choice of possibilities would almost certainly have been that the theorem was known earlier but that Pythagoras' was an independent discovery, for he believed that several ancient peoples – he named the Indians, Egyptians, and Hebrews – possessed primeval, universal wisdom (
prisca sapientia
was the later term), and Pythagoras was the first to possess it in the Greek world.
16
The theorem is so intrinsic to nature, so beautifully simple, that it would be odd if no earlier triangle user in prehistory or antiquity got curious and figured it out.

What about a more startling suggestion: that Pythagoras had nothing whatsoever to do with the discovery? Could it be that it was later credited to him only because such legends tend to become associated with famous people? Over two thousand five hundred years, numerous achievements that were not remotely Pythagorean have been carelessly credited to Pythagoras. ‘Pythagorean' or ‘of Pythagoras' have become descriptive words connoting something clever that shows mathematical insight, with an overlay of wisdom, fairness, or morality. A ‘Pythagorean cup', sold on Samos, punishes the immoderate drinker who fills it above a marked line, by allowing the entire cup of wine to drain out the bottom. Modern citizens of Samos are surprised – or at least pretend to be – that anyone would doubt this was an invention of Pythagoras. A ‘Pythagorean' formula predicts which baseball teams in America are likely to win. No one is insulted by doubts about that one.

A worse possibility
for Pythagoras' image is that he took the theorem from the Babylonians and claimed it as his own. According to Heraclitus, he ‘practised inquiry more than any other man, and selecting from these writings he made a wisdom of his own – much learning, mere fraudulence.'
[10]
It would certainly not have surprised Heraclitus if Pythagoras had stolen the Pythagorean theorem lock, stock, and barrel from the Babylonians. However, the fragments in which Heraclitus dismissed him as an impostor also placed Pythagoras high in the echelon of thinkers. Two of Heraclitus' other targets, Xenophanes and Hecataeus, were renowned polymaths. ‘Inquiry' meant not study in general but Milesian science. Most scholars think that Heraclitus had no basis for his attacks. He had an aversion to polymaths, and he was simply an ornery and contentious man being ornery and contentious. On another occasion he commented that ‘Homer should be turned out and whipped!'

If the Pythagoreans did come up with the theorem independently, the question remains whether credit should go to Pythagoras and his contemporaries or to later generations of Pythagoreans. Intemperate Heraclitus would not have been pleased to know that evidence coming from his own work places the appearance of the Pythagorean mathematical achievements in Pythagoras' lifetime: Heraclitus followed up on Pythagorean ideas about the soul and immortality and continued to develop the idea of harmony. For him, the lyre and the bow – Apollo's musical instrument and weapon – symbolised the order of nature. The bow was ‘strife', the lyre
harmonia
. The significance of the bow (‘strife') was original with Heraclitus, but the role of the lyre and
harmonia
were developments from Pythagorean thought, which suggests that the idea of connections between numerical proportions, musical consonances, and the Pythagorean numerical arrangement of the cosmos dated from the time of Pythagoras himself. Heraclitus was only one generation younger than Pythagoras.

In the first century B.C., the theorem seems to have been widely attributed to Pythagoras. A case in point: The great Roman architect Marcus Vitruvius Pollio, better known as Vitruvius, knew it well, attributed it without question to Pythagoras, and, in Book 9 of his ten-volume
De architectura
, mentioned the sacrifice to celebrate it. Apparently Vitruvius could write about Pythagoras as the discoverer of the theorem and assume that no one would gainsay him. He knew other methods of forming a right triangle, but found Pythagoras' much the easiest:

Pythagoras demonstrated the method of forming a right triangle without the aid of the instruments of artificers: and that which they scarcely, even with great trouble, exactly obtain, may be performed by his rules with great facility.

Let three rods be procured, one three feet, one four feet, and the other five feet long; and let them be so joined as to touch each other at their extremities; they will then form a triangle, one of whose angles will be a right angle. For if, on the length of each of the rods, squares be described, that whose length is three feet will have an area of nine feet; that of four, of sixteen feet; and that of five, of twenty-five feet: so that the number of feet contained in the two areas of the square of three and four feet added together, are equal to those contained in the square, whose side is five feet.
17

Where, then, does
this discussion end? In spite of the certainty that Vitruvius and his contemporaries shared, the most sceptical modern scholars think Pythagoras had nothing to do with the theorem at all. Others do not close the door to the possibilities that Pythagoras and/or his early followers may have made the discovery independently, unaware of previous knowledge of the theorem, or that they learned it elsewhere but were the first to introduce it to the Greeks.

My own conclusion is that there is no good reason to decide that Pythagoras and the Pythagoreans had nothing to do with the theorem, and several meaningful hints that they did, including the fact that Plato chose to assume that right triangles were the basic building blocks of the universe when he wrote his
Timaeus,
the dialogue most influenced by Pythagorean thinking.
[11]
If earlier knowledge of the theorem had indeed been lost, then someone had rediscovered it at about the time of Pythagoras. Of all those who were aware of right angles and triangles and used them in practical and artistic ways, the Pythagoreans were unique in their approach to the world, apparently having the motivation and leisure to give top priority to ideas and study. Their intellectual elitism kept them focused beyond the nitty-gritty of ‘what works' on the artisan level, and their musical discovery led them to think beyond number problem solving for its own sake – causing them to turn their eyes beneath the surface and view nature in an iconic way. For the Pythagoreans (as for no others among their contemporaries), the theorem would have represented an example of the wondrous underlying number structure of the universe, reinforcing their view of nature and numbers and the unity of all being, as well as the conviction that their inquiry was worthwhile, and that their secretive elitism was something to be treasured and maintained. Has any other ruling class – and the Pythagoreans seem also to have been busy ruling – had that same set of priorities? Regarding the possibility that they began with the triple, I like the fact that their having it would not imply a continuum with the Old Babylonian mathematical tradition – a continuum that scholars like Robson have convincingly argued did not exist. And in this scenario, the Babylonian evidence, instead of pulling Pythagoras off the pedestal, actually suggests a way that he and his followers could have rediscovered the theorem in the time and place that tradition has always said they did without being disillusioned too soon by the discovery of incommensurability.

Bronowski credited Pythagoras with discovering the link between the geometry of the right triangle and the truth of primordial human experience. He echoed Plato's reverence for right triangles as the basics of creation when he wrote, ‘What Pythagoras established is a fundamental characterisation of the space in which we move. It was the first time that was
translated
into numbers. And the exact fit of the numbers describes the exact laws that bind the universe.' Bronowski for that reason thought it not extravagant to call the ‘theorem of Pythagoras' ‘the most important single theorem in the whole of mathematics.'
18

But what of the ox? Did Pythagoras sacrifice it, or perhaps forty of them (some stories say), in thanksgiving for the discovery of the theorem? That Apollodorus referred to this ‘famous' story does not necessarily mean he believed it. Many dismiss the tale as impossible on the grounds that Pythagoras, who ate no meat, would not have sacrificed an ox. However, there is plenty of evidence that he had no objection to the slaughter of animals for ritual purposes. If vegetarianism is a clue, it may point in a different direction: Later Pythagoreans were more ready than early ones to believe that Pythagoras was a strict vegetarian. Burkert thought the existence of the sacrifice story ‘ought rather to be considered an indication of antiquity', weighing in on behalf of the argument that Pythagoras or his earliest followers made the discovery that spawned the tale. A later generation would not have made up this story about their hero.

[
1
]
‘Theorem' has implications, in modern terminology, that do not apply to the earliest knowledge of this rule. With that in mind, this book will nevertheless continue to use ‘theorem' to avoid seeming to mean something different from what everyone calls the Pythagorean theorem.

[
2
]
There were more than one Apollodorus, but this one was probably Apollodorus of Cyzicus, who lived in the fourth century B.C.

[
3
]
The claim has never been that Pythagoras discovered the right angle or right triangle, but that he discovered the relationship between the three sides of a right triangle – what we call the Pythagorean theorem.

[
4
]
You can think of 3–4–5 as 3 inches, 4 inches, and 5 inches, though it could just as well be centimetres, miles, parsecs or any other unit of measurement.

[
5
]
Unfortunately, most of Babylon of the early second millennium B.C. cannot now be excavated because it is well below the water table.

[
6
]
The tablet is in the Iraq Museum in Baghdad, listed in the register as 55357.

[
7
]
This mechanism, used probably in preparing calendars for planting, harvesting, and religious observances, was discovered in the wreck of a Roman ship that sank off the island of Antikythera in about 65 B.C. It was more technically complex than any known instrument for at least a millennium afterwards.

[
8
]
Political and social upheaval may have created disruptions. Or the fault may lie with modern scholarship, for few sites have been dug from these periods. They do not attract many scholars, partly because the documents are terribly difficult to decipher. Furthermore, as the very complicated cuneiform script gave way to alphabetic Aramaic, documents tended to be written on perishable and recyclable materials. The old Sumerian, Akkadian, and the cuneiform script were used for fewer purposes, mathematics apparently not being one of them, and even where cuneiform was used, it was often on wax-covered ivory or wooden writing boards that were erased for reuse or have not survived.

[
9
]
A rational number is a whole number or a fraction that is made by dividing any whole number by another whole number: 1⁄2, 4/5, 2/7, etc. An irrational number is a number that cannot be expressed as a fraction, that is, as a ratio of two whole numbers. The square root of 2 was probably found by Pythagoreans, working from their theory of odd and even numbers, possibly as early as about 450 B.C., and surely by 420, fifty to eighty years after Pythagoras' death. Plato knew of the square roots of numbers up to 17.

[
10
]
Though Heraclitus seems forthright and outspoken in the fragments about Pythagoras, he was known to be no easy read. His contemporaries dubbed him Heraclitus the Obscure and Heraclitus the Riddler. A story circulated in the time of Diogenes Laertius that when Socrates received a copy of a book by Heraclitus, he commented: ‘What I understand is splendid; and so too, I'm sure, is what I don't understand – but it would take a Delian diver to get to the bottom of it.'

[
11
]
See Chapter 9.

Other books

In God's Name by David Yallop
Miracle by Connie Willis
Jo's Journey by Nikki Tate
Cates, Kimberly by Angel's Fall
Mind Over Psyche by Karina L. Fabian
Blind Fury by Linda I. Shands
Death Train to Boston by Dianne Day